• Subscriber Services
  • For Authors
  • Publications
  • Archaeology
  • Art & Architecture
  • Bilingual dictionaries
  • Classical studies
  • Encyclopedias
  • English Dictionaries and Thesauri
  • Language reference
  • Linguistics
  • Media studies
  • Medicine and health
  • Names studies
  • Performing arts
  • Science and technology
  • Social sciences
  • Society and culture
  • Overview Pages
  • Subject Reference
  • English Dictionaries
  • Bilingual Dictionaries

Recently viewed (0)

  • Save Search
  • Share This Facebook LinkedIn Twitter

Related Content

Related overviews.

Newton's laws of motion

More Like This

Show all results sharing this subject:

crucial experiment

Quick reference.

An experiment held to decide with certainty between two rival hypotheses about some matter. Famous examples include Eddington's observation of the bending of light rays by the sun during the eclipse of 1919, held to decisively uphold general relativity against Newtonian mechanics, or the observation of weight gain during combustion, held to decide for the theory that combustion is oxidation and against the view that it consists in loss of phlogiston. In practice experiments require a great deal of scene-setting and agreement on what would count as an ad hoc hypothesis before they play such a decisive role, so that rational disagreement on whether one or another rival is really refuted is both possible in theory and often found in practice.

From:   crucial experiment   in  The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy »

Subjects: Philosophy

Related content in Oxford Reference

Reference entries.

View all related items in Oxford Reference »

Search for: 'crucial experiment' in Oxford Reference »

  • Oxford University Press

PRINTED FROM OXFORD REFERENCE (www.oxfordreference.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2023. All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single entry from a reference work in OR for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice ).

date: 17 August 2024

  • Cookie Policy
  • Privacy Policy
  • Legal Notice
  • Accessibility
  • [81.177.182.174]
  • 81.177.182.174

Character limit 500 /500

  • Institutional Login

Access to the full content is only available to members of institutions that have purchased access. If you belong to such an institution, please log in or find out more about how to order .

Loading content

We were unable to load the content

Article Summary

  • content locked Bibliography

Crucial experiments

  • Achinstein, Peter

A ‘crucial experiment’ allegedly establishes the truth of one of a set of competing theories. Francis Bacon ( 1620 ) held that such experiments are frequent in the empirical sciences and are particularly important for terminating an investigation. These claims were denied by Pierre Duhem ( 1905 ), who maintained that crucial experiments are impossible in the physical sciences because they require a complete enumeration of all possible theories to explain a phenomenon – something that cannot be achieved. Despite Duhem , scientists frequently regard certain experiments as crucial in the sense that the experimental result helps make one theory among a set of competitors very probable and the others very improbable, given what is currently known.

Related Searches

  • Philosophy of science

Thank you for visiting Quantum Diaries, which from 2005 to 2016 hosted blogs by scientists from particle physics institutions around the world.

To see new posts, visit the Interactions collaboration 's new blog, Particle People , which hops from country to country, highlighting a new blogger involved in particle physics research each month.

Quantum Diaries

crucial experiment definition

  • About Quantum Diaries

Latest Posts

crucial experiment definition

  • 2016.08.01 | Particles over Politics: The More the Merrier
  • 2016.02.29 | The Four-Leafed Clovers of Subatomic Particles: Tetraquarks
  • 2016.02.01 | Spun out of proportion: The Proton Spin Crisis

crucial experiment definition

  • University of Maryland
  • 2015.04.16 | Building a Neutrino Detector
  • 2014.11.06 | Cool Little Neutrinos
  • 2014.08.05 | Super Fracking and Physics

crucial experiment definition

  • Open University
  • United Kingdom
  • 2015.02.04 | Physics + wine = plasma + fun
  • 2014.12.07 | CERN appoints new Director-General
  • 2014.08.29 | Coffee and Code (Part Deux)

crucial experiment definition

  • Netherlands
  • 2015.04.07 | AFTER@LHC: Going beyond the collider
  • 2015.01.12 | United for peace
  • 2014.12.19 | A transverse look into the proton

crucial experiment definition

  • Switzerland
  • 2014.07.29 | CERN through the eyes of a young scientist
  • 2014.07.14 | Two anomalies worth noticing
  • 2014.07.11 | Happy birthday, dear boson!

crucial experiment definition

  • Randle-Conde
  • Université Libre de Bruxelles
  • 2016.04.01 | Lab news
  • 2015.04.01 | LHC Run 2 cancelled, CERN closes doors
  • 2015.03.02 | 30 reasons why you shouldn’t be a particle physicist

crucial experiment definition

  • Vancouver, BC
  • 2015.02.02 | Collision of Art & Science: A head above water
  • 2014.05.01 | A fish out of water
  • 2014.03.14 | Where have all the great ones gone?

crucial experiment definition

  • Yale University
  • 2015.05.08 | Anti-Matters: The Latest and Greatest from the Alpha Magnetic Spectrometer
  • 2015.01.14 | A New Year’s Resolution: Read More Papers!
  • 2014.09.25 | Dark Skies II: Indirect Detection and The Quest for the Smoking Gun

crucial experiment definition

  • University College London
  • 2015.12.14 | New LUX Results on WIMP-Nucleon Scattering
  • 2015.09.08 | About to start a Physics degree? Hold on tight…
  • 2015.03.25 | Vote LUX, and give an underdog a chance

crucial experiment definition

  • Univ. of Pittsburgh
  • 2015.09.22 | Neutrinoless Double Beta Decay and the Quest for Majorana Neutrinos
  • 2015.05.18 | Drell-Yan, Drell-Yan with Jets, Drell-Yan with all the Jets
  • 2015.02.04 | Excited Quarks and Early Discoveries at LHC Run II

crucial experiment definition

  • 2015.04.17 | Life Underground: Anything Anyone Would Teach Me
  • 2015.04.09 | CUORE-0 Results Tour Kicks Off
  • 2015.02.07 | Sonic Copper Cleaning

crucial experiment definition

  • University of Michigan
  • 2016.02.10 | The Problem with B.o.B. – Science and the flat earth
  • 2015.01.18 | The Ties That Bind

crucial experiment definition

  • 2016.03.21 | Live Blogging of the LHCb Bs pi result
  • 2015.07.15 | Finding a five-leafed clover
  • 2015.03.31 | CERN Had Dark Energy All Along; Uses It To Fuel Researchers

crucial experiment definition

  • Batavia, IL
  • 2015.10.12 | A measurement to watch
  • 2015.08.27 | The Tesla experiment
  • 2015.08.12 | MicroBooNE sees first cosmic muons

crucial experiment definition

  • Imperial College London
  • 2015.10.29 | @CMSVoices
  • 2015.07.16 | Nerds and Names
  • 2015.04.07 | Choose as Many as You Like

crucial experiment definition

  • 2015.01.09 | Physics and outreach: my social media adventure

crucial experiment definition

  • Long Island, NY
  • 2014.06.19 | Physicists at Large Hadron Collider Physics Conference Look Forward
  • 2014.03.04 | Particle Beam Cancer Therapy: The Promise and Challenges
  • 2013.03.11 | Polarized Proton Data Flowing With RHIC Running

crucial experiment definition

  • 2015.02.04 | What BICEP2 Got Right
  • 2014.12.30 | Announcing the launch of a way to ‘crowdfund’ physics!
  • 2014.10.29 | Interstellar the movie is coming soon — and it’s a biggie

crucial experiment definition

  • University of Melbourne
  • 2015.07.04 | Why Dark Matter Exists: Believing Without Seeing
  • 2015.02.04 | Where Do I Come From?
  • 2015.01.08 | How to build a universe

crucial experiment definition

  • 2015.12.21 | LHC 2015: what’s different in four years?
  • 2015.12.05 | What have we learned from the LHC in 2015?
  • 2015.08.27 | Double time

crucial experiment definition

  • 2015.08.18 | Pour une physique nucléaire accessible à tous
  • 2015.02.26 | Twitter, Planck et les supernovae
  • 2013.10.11 | Prix Nobel de physique 2013 : “le succès de toute une communauté”

Byron Jennings | TRIUMF | Canada

View blog | read bio, the role of the crucial experiment.

Normal 0 false false false EN-CA JA X-NONE

The idea of a crucial experiment that decisively confirms a model goes back at least to Francis Bacon (1561 – 1626) who used the term instantia cruci. Later, the term experimentum crucis was coined by Robert Hooke (1635 – 1703) and used by Isaac Newton (1642 – 1727), in particular with regard to his theory of light. Alternatively, Pierre Duhem (1861 – 1916) strongly disagreed with the possibility of crucial experiments. Somewhat in anticipation of Thomas Kuhn’s (1922–1996) paradigms , Duhem realized that scientific theories or models do not stand alone, but rather come coupled with auxiliary assumptions. Was what Galileo saw through the telescope features of the heavens, or only of his telescope, as some of his detractors claimed? One has to consider the combined heavens-telescope system to decide. When the detector is as complex as the ATLAS detector at CERN the question is even more apropos.

Karl Popper (1902 – 1994) refined the idea of the crucial experiment to one that falsifies a given model. But the Duhem-Quine hypothesis , a variation of Duhem’s idea, makes the point that falsification, at least in its naïve form, falls victim to same holistic argument: we can never test a single model in isolation. So is the idea of a crucial experiment just a will-o-the-wisp that vanishes on more careful evaluation?

We can think of many examples: Sir Arthur Eddington`s measurement of the bending of star light by the sun, the discovery of high-temperature superconductors, the measurement of the three degree microwave background, the Michelson–Morley experiment, and so on. Did none of these play a critical role in the history of science? I would suggest they did, but not in the simple manner suggested by Bacon or Popper.

Consider the Michelson–Morley experiment in 1887. Scientists did not do a Chicken Little impersonation and run around claiming the sky was falling or, in this case, that Newton (Newton`s laws of motion) and Maxwell (electromagnetism) were wrong. Rather, they started trying to understand what the explanation could be. This led to ideas like ether drag (the earth entraining the ether) or Lorentz-Fitzgerald contraction (the idea that objects shorten in the direction of motion). The latter idea was developed and expanded upon by Lorentz and Poincaré who developed the math for special relativity. Einstein claimed he was unaware of the Michelson–Morley experiment, but he was certainly aware of Lorentz`s early attempts to understand that experiment. Thus, the Michelson–Morley experiment started a chain of events that inexorably lead to special relativity, not in one easy step, but eventually and inevitably. If special relativity had been proposed thirty years sooner, it would have been treated as a curiosity like the Copernicus model when it was first proposed.

As another example, consider the measurement of the bending of light by the sun. The general theory of relativity and classical mechanics differ by a factor of two. Eddington`s 1919 experiment gave a result closer to general relativity and hence contributed to the early acceptance of general relativity (not that people are not still trying to test it; that is as it should be). A more striking example was the discovery of the three-degree kelvin cosmic microwave background. Before then, there were two models, both with strong support: the steady-state model and the big bang model. While the microwave background was a big boost for the big bang model, the solid state model did not give up without a struggle. There were various attempts to describe the microwave background in the solid state model but they were too little too late. Like the Michelson–Morley experiment, the discovery of the microwave background started a chain reaction that led to the acceptance of one model and the rejection of another.

Perhaps the best way of thinking of crucial experiments is not that they prove (that ugly word) one model better than another, but that they serve as a catalyst. Or perhaps, one can think of a super-cooled fluid that when slightly disturbed, suddenly solidifies . The same phenomenon is seen with people. A group are sitting at lunch and when one gets up to go and they all go, but only if the circumstances are right. Consider the discovery of the J/Ψ particle. The time was right and the background had been prepared so that when it was discovered, the particle physics community solidified around the quark model. Similarly, you can consider Galileo turning his telescope on the heavens as providing the catalyst for the acceptance of the heliocentric model.

Like models, experimental results do not exist in isolation. Rather, they build on each other and are given meaning by the prevailing models. The role of crucial experiments should be seen in relation to that milieu. They do not single handedly overturn or confirm the status quo, but rather, start chains of events that lead to or act as tipping points for the establishment of new paradigms. Thus, crucial experiments do exist but not in the naïve manner envisioned by Bacon, Hooke, or Popper.

Additional posts in this series will appear most Friday afternoons at 3:30 pm Vancouver time. To receive a reminder follow me on Twitter: @musquod.

The idea of a crucial experiment that decisively confirms a model goes back at least to Francis Bacon (1561 – 1626) who used the term instantia cruci. Later, the term experimentum crucis was coined by Robert Hooke (1635 – 1703) and used by Isaac Newton (1642 – 1727), in particular with regard to his theory of light. Alternatively, Pierre Duhem (1861 – 19 16) strongly disagreed with the possibility of crucial experiments. Somewhat in anticipation of Thomas Kuhn’s (1922–1996) paradigms , Duhem realized that scientific theories or models do not stand alone, but rather come coupled with auxiliary assumptions. Was what Galileo saw through the telescope features of the heavens, or only of his telescope, as some of his detractors claimed? One has to consider the combined heavens-telescope system to decide. When the detector is as complex as the ATLAS detector at CERN the question is even more apropos.

Consider the Michelson–Morley experiment [W1] in 1887. Scientists did not do a Chicken Little impersonation and run around claiming the sky was falling or, in this case, that Newton (Newton`s laws of motion) and Maxwell (electromagnetism) were wrong. Rather, they started trying to understand what the explanation could be. This led to ideas like ether drag (the earth entraining the ether) or Lorentz-Fitzgerald contraction (the idea that objects shorten in the direction of motion). The latter idea was developed and expanded upon by Lorentz and Poincaré who developed the math for special relativity. Einstein claimed he was unaware of the Michelson–Morley experiment, but he was certainly aware of Lorentz`s early attempts to understand that experiment. Thus, the Michelson–Morley experiment started a chain of events that inexorably lead to special relativity, not in one easy step, but eventually and inevitably. If special relativity had been proposed thirty years sooner, it would have been treated as a curiosity like the Copernicus model when it was first proposed.

Perhaps the best way of thinking of crucial experiments is not that they prove (that ugly word) one model better than another, but that they serve as a catalyst. Or perhaps, one can think of a super-cooled fluid that when slightly disturbed, suddenly solidifies [W2] . The same phenomenon is seen with people. A group are sitting at lunch and when one gets up to go and they all go, but only if the circumstances are right. Consider the discovery of the J/ Ψ particle. The time was right and the background had been prepared so that when it was discovered, the particle physics community solidified around the quark model. Similarly, you can consider Galileo turning his telescope on the heavens a������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������s���������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������

Share

Tags: crucial experiment , Hooke , Philosophy of science , Pierre Duhem , Popper

Comments are closed.

Laboratories

  • View Blog (English)
  • Read Bio (English)
  • View Blog (French)
  • Read Bio (French)
  • CERN through the eyes of a young scientist
  • Two anomalies worth noticing
  • Deux petites anomalies remarquées
  • Bon anniversaire, cher boson!
  • Collision of Art & Science: A head above water
  • A fish out of water
  • A measurement to watch
  • The Tesla experiment

Brookhaven National Laboratory

  • Physicists at Large Hadron Collider Physics Conference Look Forward
  • Particle Beam Cancer Therapy: The Promise and Challenges
  • Lectures of EDIT 2013 are broadcasted by the Ustream
  • 全国各地の高校生、素粒子実験を体験 ‐Belle Plus2011開催‐
  • The Delirium over Beryllium
  • What is "Model Building"?
  • Live Blogging of the LHCb Bs pi result
  • LHC 2015: what's different in four years?
  • Pour une physique nucléaire accessible à tous
  • Twitter, Planck et les supernovae
  • The forgotten life of Einstein’s wife
  • La vie oubliée de la femme d’Einstein
  • Latest news from outer space on dark matter
  • Du beau pain sur la planche pour la matière sombre
  • Solving the Measurement Problem (Guest Post)

Share it Here

A project of the Interaction Collaboration

  • Interactions.org Home
  • Latest News
  • 2Asymptotia
  • Cocktail Party Physics
  • Cosmic Diary
  • Cosmic Variance
  • Life as a physicist
  • Physics and Physicists
  • Physics arXiv blog
  • Resonaances
  • Stephanie Majewski blog
  • symmetry breaking
  • Symmetry factor
  • The X-Change Files
  • US/LHC blogs

©2024 Interactions.org

Psychology Dictionary

CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT

a trial and error procedure built in a way that the outcome will conclude which of the two converse theories has postulated the accurate prediction .

Avatar photo

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Latest Posts

crucial experiment definition

What Happens At An ADHD Assessment

crucial experiment definition

A Quick Look at the History Behind Hypnosis

crucial experiment definition

A Brief History of Brainwashing: The Science of Thought Control

crucial experiment definition

A Deep Dive into the Social Psychology of Leadership

crucial experiment definition

Counseling Approaches to Client Care: Theories to Apply in Practice

crucial experiment definition

The Future Of Education: Can You Earn A Psychology Degree Online?

crucial experiment definition

Insomnia & Mental Illness: What is the Correlation?

Psychology of Decision Making

Stop Guessing: Here Are 3 Steps to Data-Driven Psychological Decisions

crucial experiment definition

Getting Help with Grief: Understanding Therapy & How It Can Help

crucial experiment definition

Exploring the Psychology of Risk and Reward

crucial experiment definition

Understanding ADHD in Women: Symptoms, Treatment & Support

crucial experiment definition

Meeting the Milestones: A Guide to Piaget's Child Developmental Stages

Popular psychology terms, medical model, hypermnesia, affirmation, brainwashing, backup reinforcer, message-learning approach, affiliative behavior, behavioral modeling, approach motivation, social pressure.

Conceptual Change, Crucial Experiments and Auxiliary Hypotheses. A Theoretical Contribution

  • Published: 30 July 2010
  • Volume 44 , pages 288–298, ( 2010 )

Cite this article

crucial experiment definition

  • Marcelo Leonardo Levinas 1 &
  • Mario Carretero 2  

157 Accesses

Explore all metrics

Theories about conceptual change have been generally related to historical and philosophical analysis of science. Yet, there is still much debate on how ideas coming from the history of science and their implications can be applied in this field. Our study intends to investigate the complex structure of conceptual change, by making use of some particularly representative features of the History and Philosophy of science, while considering the structure of so-called crucial experiments and the specific role of implicit hypotheses. Due to their historical importance and logical reasoning aspects, examining these issues may contribute to understand how conceptual change may take place.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

crucial experiment definition

Constructivism/Conceptual Change

crucial experiment definition

Interests in Conceptual Changes: A Frame Analysis

crucial experiment definition

The externalist challenge to conceptual engineering

Arabatzis, T., & Kindi, V. (2008). The problem of conceptual change in the philosophy and history of science. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International handbook of research on conceptual change (pp. 345–373). New York: Routledge.

Google Scholar  

Brewer, W. & Samarapungavan, A., (1991). Children’s theories versus scientific theories: Differences in reasoning or differences in knowledge? Cognition and the symbolic processes: Applied and ecological perspectives (pp. 209–232). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

Brown, H. (1977). Perception, theory and commitment. The new philosophy of science . Chicago: Precedent.

Cassini, A., & Levinas, M. L. (2005). “La interpretación radical del experimento de Michelson-Morley por la relatividad especial” (“The Radical Interpretation of Michelson-Morley Experiment by Special Relativity”). Scientiae Studia, 3 (4), 547–581.

Article   Google Scholar  

Cassini, A., & Levinas, M. L. (2009). “El éter relativista: Un cambio conceptual inconcluso”, (“The Relatistic Ether: An Unfinished Conceptual Change”). Crítica (Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, UNAM, México), 41 (123), 3–38.

Copi, I. (1953). Introduction to logic . New York: MacMillan.

Chin, C. A., & Brewer, W. F. (1993). The role of anomalous data in knowledge acquisition. Review of Educational Research, 63 (1), 1–49.

Duhem, P. (1982). The aim and structure of physical theory . Princeton: Princeton University Press. Originally published in French: La théorie physique: Son objet, sa structure , 1906.

Duit, R., Treagust, D. F., & Widodo, A. (2008). Teaching science for conceptual change: Theory and practice. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International handbook of research on conceptual change (pp. 629–646). New York: Routledge.

Duschl, R. (2008). Science education in 3 part harmony: Balancing conceptual, epistemic and social learning goals. In J. Green, A. Luke, & G. Kelly (Eds.), Review of research in education, Vol. 32 . Washington DC: AERA.

Duschl, R., & Grandy, R. (Eds.). (2008). Establishing a consensus agenda for K-12 science inquiry . Rotterdam: Sense.

Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1938). The evolution of physics . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hacking, I. (1988). Philosophers of experiment. PSA, 2 , 147–156.

Hartman, H., & Nissim-Sabat, C. (2003). On Mach’s Critique of Newton and Copernicus. American Journal of Physics, 71 (11), 1163–1169.

Lakatos, I. (1971). History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions. In R. Buck & R. Cohen (Eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science , vol. VIII (pp. 91–136). Reidel: Dordrecht.

Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems . Berkeley: University of California Press.

Lehrer, R., Schauble, L., & Lucas, D. (2008). Supporting development of the epistemology of inquiry. Cognitive Development , 23 (4), 512–529.

Levinas, M. L., & Umérez, N. (2000). Field interaction and anomalies in astrophysical and cosmological phenomena. General Relativity and Gravitation Journal, 32 (1), 175–182.

Limón, M. (2001). On the cognitive conflict as an instructional strategy for conceptual change: A critical appraisal. Learning and Instruction, 11 (4–5), 357–380.

Limón, M., & Carretero, M. (1999). Conflicting data and conceptual change in history experts. In W. Schnotz, S. Vosniadou, & M. Carretero (Eds.), New perspectives in conceptual change (pp. 137–160). Oxford: Elsevier.

Limón, M., & Mason, L. (Eds.). (2002). Reconsidering conceptual change: Issues in theory and practice . New York: Kluwer.

Nersessian, J. (2008). Mental modeling in conceptual change. In S. Vosniadou (Ed.), International handbook of research on conceptual change . New York: Routledge.

Popper, K. (1972). The logic of scientific discovery . New York: Routledge.

Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., & Gertzog, W. A. (1982). Accommodation of a scientific conception: Toward a theory of conceptual change. Science & Education, 66 (2), 211–227.

Pozo, J. I., & Carretero, M. (1994). Causal theories, reasoning strategies and cognitive conflicts in Newtonian mechanics. In A. Demetriou (Ed.), Neopiagetian theories of cognitive development. Implications and applications for education (pp. 231–255). London: Routledge.

Quine, W. (1961). From a logical point of view (2nd ed.). New York: Harper.

Schnotz, W., Vosniadou, S., & Carretero, M. (Eds.). (1999). New perspectives in conceptual change . Oxford: Elsevier.

Sinatra, G. M., & Pintrich, P. R. (Eds.). (2003). Intentional conceptual change . Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

Vosniadou, S. (Ed.). (2008). International handbook of research on conceptual change . New York: Routledge.

Vosniadou, S., Baltas, A., & Vamvakoussi, X. (Eds.). (2007). Reframing the conceptual change approach in learning and instruction . Oxford: Elsevier.

Zammito, J. H. (2004). A nice derangement of epistemes: Post-positivism in the study of science from Quine to Latour . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was partially written and revised with the support of the Fellowship (2009/2010) to the second author at the D. Rockefeller Center (Harvard University), where David Perkins made some suggestions which we would like also to thank. Also it was funded by Universidad de Buenos Aires—grant UBACyT F086—and CONICET (National Council of Science and Technology, Argentina)—grant PIP 6021—, coordinated by the first author, and also the projects Consolider SEJ 2006-15461 (Spanish Ministry of Education) and PICT-2005-34778 from ANPCYT (Argentina) coordinated by the second author.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

University of Buenos Aires and National Council for Science and Technological Research (CONICET), Buenos Aires, Argentina

Marcelo Leonardo Levinas

Universidad Autónoma de Madrid, Spain and Facultad Latinoamericana de Ciencias Sociales (FLACSO), Buenos Aires, Argentina

Mario Carretero

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcelo Leonardo Levinas .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Levinas, M.L., Carretero, M. Conceptual Change, Crucial Experiments and Auxiliary Hypotheses. A Theoretical Contribution. Integr. psych. behav. 44 , 288–298 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-010-9139-2

Download citation

Published : 30 July 2010

Issue Date : December 2010

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-010-9139-2

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Conceptual change
  • Epistemology
  • Philosophy of science
  • History of science
  • Crucial experiments
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research
  • ABBREVIATIONS
  • BIOGRAPHIES
  • CALCULATORS
  • CONVERSIONS
  • DEFINITIONS

Definitions.net

  Vocabulary      

What does experimentum crucis mean?

Definitions for experimentum crucis ex·per·i·men·tum cru·cis, this dictionary definitions page includes all the possible meanings, example usage and translations of the word experimentum crucis ., wiktionary rate this definition: 5.0 / 1 vote.

experimentum crucis noun

A "crucial experiment"; a conclusive test to decide between different hypotheses.

Etymology: Modern Latin.

Wikipedia Rate this definition: 0.0 / 0 votes

Experimentum crucis

In science, an experimentum crucis (English: crucial experiment or critical experiment) is an experiment capable of decisively determining whether or not a particular hypothesis or theory is superior to all other hypotheses or theories whose acceptance is currently widespread in the scientific community. In particular, such an experiment must typically be able to produce a result that rules out all other hypotheses or theories if true, thereby demonstrating that under the conditions of the experiment (i.e., under the same external circumstances and for the same "input variables" within the experiment), those hypotheses and theories are proven false but the experimenter's hypothesis is not ruled out. For an opposite view putting into question the decisive value of the experimentum crucis in choosing one hypothesis or theory over its rivals, see Pierre Duhem.

Wikidata Rate this definition: 4.0 / 1 vote

In the sciences, an experimentum crucis is an experiment capable of decisively determining whether or not a particular hypothesis or theory is superior to all other hypotheses or theories whose acceptance is currently widespread in the scientific community. In particular, such an experiment must typically be able to produce a result that rules out all other hypotheses or theories if true, thereby demonstrating that under the conditions of the experiment, those hypotheses and theories are proven false but the experimenter's hypothesis is not ruled out. Francis Bacon in his Novum Organum first described the concept of a situation in which one theory but not others would hold true, using the name instantia crucis; the phrase experimentum crucis, denoting the deliberate creation of such a situation for the purpose of testing the rival theories, was later coined by Robert Hooke and then famously used by Isaac Newton. The production of such an experiment is considered necessary for a particular hypothesis or theory to be considered an established part of the body of scientific knowledge. It is not unusual in the history of science for theories to be developed fully before producing a critical experiment. A given theory which is in accordance with known experiment but which has not yet produced a critical experiment is typically considered worthy of exploration in order to discover such an experimental test.

How to pronounce experimentum crucis?

Alex US English David US English Mark US English Daniel British Libby British Mia British Karen Australian Hayley Australian Natasha Australian Veena Indian Priya Indian Neerja Indian Zira US English Oliver British Wendy British Fred US English Tessa South African

How to say experimentum crucis in sign language?

Chaldean Numerology

The numerical value of experimentum crucis in Chaldean Numerology is: 9

Pythagorean Numerology

The numerical value of experimentum crucis in Pythagorean Numerology is: 2

  • ^  Wiktionary https://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/Experimentum_Crucis
  • ^  Wikipedia https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Experimentum_Crucis
  • ^  Wikidata https://www.wikidata.org/w/index.php?search=experimentum crucis

Translations for experimentum crucis

From our multilingual translation dictionary.

  • experimentum crucis German
  • experimentum Crucisの Japanese
  • experimentum十字 Chinese

Word of the Day

Would you like us to send you a free new word definition delivered to your inbox daily.

Please enter your email address:

Citation

Use the citation below to add this definition to your bibliography:.

Style: MLA Chicago APA

"experimentum crucis." Definitions.net. STANDS4 LLC, 2024. Web. 17 Aug. 2024. < https://www.definitions.net/definition/experimentum+crucis >.

Cite.Me

Discuss these experimentum crucis definitions with the community:

 width=

Report Comment

We're doing our best to make sure our content is useful, accurate and safe. If by any chance you spot an inappropriate comment while navigating through our website please use this form to let us know, and we'll take care of it shortly.

You need to be logged in to favorite .

Create a new account.

Your name: * Required

Your email address: * Required

Pick a user name: * Required

Username: * Required

Password: * Required

Forgot your password?    Retrieve it

Are we missing a good definition for experimentum crucis ? Don't keep it to yourself...

Image credit, the web's largest resource for, definitions & translations, a member of the stands4 network, image or illustration of.

  • experimentum crucis

crucial experiment definition

Free, no signup required :

Add to chrome, add to firefox, browse definitions.net, are you a words master, express strong disapproval of, Nearby & related entries:.

  • experimentee
  • experimenter noun
  • experimenter bias noun
  • experimentist
  • experiments
  • experimetalist
  • experinenting
  • experrection
  • expert infantryman badge

Alternative searches for experimentum crucis :

  • Search for experimentum crucis on Amazon

crucial experiment definition

Search & Browse

  • Simple Search
  • Advanced Search
  • Browse by Author
  • Browse by Subject
  • Browse by Year
  • Browse by Conferences/Volumes
  • Browse Open Access Journals
  • Browse Open Access Books
  • Latest Additions
  • Browse the PhilMath Archive

Information

  • About the Archive
  • Archive Policy
  • Journal Eprint Policies
(2007) [Preprint]

Going back at least to Duhem, there is a tradition of thinking that crucial experiments are impossible in science. I analyse Duhem’s arguments and show that they are based on the excessively strong assumption that only deductive reasoning is permissible in experimental science. This opens the possibility that some principle of inductive inference could provide a sufficient reason for preferring one among a group of hypotheses on the basis of an appropriately controlled experiment. To be sure, there are analogues to Duhem’s problems that pertain to inductive inference. Using a famous experiment from the history of molecular biology as an example, I show that an experimentalist version of inference to the best explanation (IBE) does a better job in handling these problems than other accounts of scientific inference. Furthermore, I introduce a concept of experimental mechanism and show that it can guide inferences from data within an IBE-based framework for induction.

| | | | |
|
Item Type: Preprint
Creators:
CreatorsEmailORCID
Weber, Marcel

Available Versions of this Item

  • The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem’s Problems and Inference to the Best Explanation. (deposited 03 Mar 2008) [Currently Displayed]

Monthly Views for the past 3 years

Monthly downloads for the past 3 years, plum analytics, actions (login required).

View Item

ULS D-Scribe

D-Scribe

This site is hosted by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program

Philsci Archive is powered by EPrints 3 which is developed by the School of Electronics and Computer Science at the University of Southampton. More information and software credits .

Get Alerts for All New Posts

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Pierre Duhem

Pierre Duhem (1861–1916) was a French physicist and historian and philosopher of science. As a physicist, he championed “energetics,” holding generalized thermodynamics as foundational for physical theory, that is, thinking that all of chemistry and physics, including mechanics, electricity, and magnetism, should be derivable from thermodynamic first principles. In philosophy of science, he is best known for his work on the relation between theory and experiment, arguing that hypotheses are not straightforwardly refuted by experiment and that there are no crucial experiments in science. In history of science, he produced massive groundbreaking work in medieval science and defended a thesis of continuity between medieval and early modern science.

1. Life and Works

2.1 against “newtonian method”: the duhem thesis, 2.2 against “cartesian method”: metaphysics and models, 2.3 later developments, 3. history of science, primary sources, secondary sources, other internet resources, related entries.

Pierre Maurice Marie Duhem was born on June 10, 1861, in Paris, in a modest neighborhood on the Rue des Jeûneurs, near the Grands Boulevards, just South of Montmartre. His father, Pierre-Joseph Duhem, was of Flemish origin, the oldest child of a large family who lived in the French northern industrial city of Roubaix, near the Belgian border. After the death of his parents, Pierre-Joseph was forced to discontinue his studies with the Jesuits in order to provide for the family. He worked in the textile industry as a sales representative, but never abandoned his love of learning; it is said that, late in life, he was seen everywhere with the work of a Latin author under his arm. Pierre Duhem’s mother, Marie-Alexandrine Fabre, descended on her mother’s side from the Hubault-Delormes, a bourgeois family who had settled in Paris during the seventeenth century. Her father’s family had originally come from the southern town of Cabesprine, near Carcasonne, and it was there, in a house they still maintained and to which Pierre returned most summers, that he died on September 14, 1916.

The Duhems made sure that Pierre was well educated. Starting at the age of seven he was given private lessons with a small group of students, on grammar, arithmetic, Latin, and catechism. A letter he wrote about the siege of Chateaudun he experienced in October 1870 attests to his being already a literate writer by the age of nine. The young Duhem was witness to some troubling times, with the Franco-Prussian War raging until the armistice in February 1871 and the Paris Commune in March. The Duhems had avoided the advance of the Prussians against Paris but were caught up in the siege of Chateaudun; they barely escaped to Bordeaux, returning to Paris after the armistice and just before the Paris Commune. That social experiment lasted only two months, though it set the stage for some wide-ranging transformations to French culture that were to have great consequences when they were later established permanently. Among the Commune’s decrees were the separation of church from state, the rendering of all church property into public property, and the exclusion of religion from schools. The Duhems did not approve of these measures and were particularly chagrined by some of the extreme actions taken by the most radical elements of the Commune, such as the desecration of churches and graveyards. For the Duhems, the Commune was a paradigm of anarchy and irreligion.

The Fall of 1872 brought two great tragedies to the Duhem family: a diphtheria epidemic killed Pierre’s younger sister Antoinette and his recently born brother Jean, leaving only Pierre and Antoinette’s twin sister Marie. Pierre continued his education (as demi-pensionnaire ) at a Catholic school, the Collège Stanislas in Paris, in 1872 and for the next ten years. The mature Duhem recalled his college days as most formative. In particular, he singled out his science teacher as an important influence:

Let us return to some twenty-five years back to the time when we received our first initiation as a physicist in the mathematics classes of the Collège Stanislas. The person who gave us this initiation, Jules Moutier, was an ingenious theorist; his critical sense, ever aware and extremely perspicacious, distinguished with sure accuracy the weak point of many a system that others accepted without dispute; proofs of his inquiring mind are not lacking, and physical chemistry owes him one of its most important laws. It was this teacher who planted in us our admiration for physical theory and the desire to contribute to its progress. … Being a disciple of Moutier, it was as a convinced partisan of mechanism that we approached the courses in physics pursued at the Ecole Normale. (1914, 417–18; 1954, 275–76.)

Duhem’s science teacher Jules Moutier went on to teach at the Ecole Polytechnique and to publish a number of texts, including La thermodynamique et ses principales applications (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1885). Duhem recognized in his theory of chemical dissociation and in his thermodynamics generally a first enunciation of the chemical theories that Josiah Willard Gibbs, an important later influence on Duhem, was to develop more fully.

In 1882 Duhem enrolled at the prestigious secular institution of higher education, the Ecole Normale Supérieure. When he entered the Ecole Normale he was first in his class in the Science Section, out of the approximately 30 students chosen from the best 800 or so graduates in France that year, and he remained first throughout his years there. The curriculum at the Ecole Normale usually lasted three years; Duhem was granted a fourth year and stayed on a fifth year as agrégé préparateur . He received a license in mathematics and another in physics at the end of academic year 1883–84. In his final year, Duhem was offered a position in Louis Pasteur’s laboratory as a chemist-bacteriologist, though he refused it because of his desire to work in theoretical physics.

One of the turning points in Duhem’s career occurred during academic year 1884–85, while he was only a third-year student. Duhem presented a thesis in physics for his doctorate. The thesis, on thermodynamic potential, Le potentiel thermodynamique et ses applications à la mécanique chimique et à l’étude des phénomènes électriques , was rejected by a panel composed of three scholars: the physicist Gabriel Lippmann and the mathematicians Charles Hermite and Emile Picard. The panel, chaired by Lippmann, seems to have made a political decision. The prestigious French scientific publisher, Hermann, published a version of the thesis the following year. Duhem defended another thesis in applied mathematics, on the theory of magnetization by induction, Sur l’aimantation par influence , and received his doctorate in October 1888; this time, the physicist Edmond Bouty, the mathematician Gaston Darboux, and the mathematician-physicist Henri Poincaré constituted the panel that accepted the dissertation. It would be difficult to understand fully these events without delving deeply into the social, cultural, and intellectual context of France at the end of the nineteenth century. At a time when French scientists were predominantly liberal and anti-clerical, Duhem was openly conservative and deeply religious; he was also stubborn and often contentious. The structure of French academia was surely also a factor in the affair. However, the specific motives generally cited in the case were Lipmann’s “jealousy” and the fact that Duhem’s thesis refuted the principle of maximum work: that chemical changes tend spontaneously to produce maximum heat. It was one of the cherished theses of Marcellin Berthelot, Lippmann’s friend and a significant power in the French scientific establishment. It was reported that Berthelot had said: “This young man will never teach in Paris.” Berthelot’s edict came true. Duhem spent his academic career in provincial universities far from Paris, the center of academic life in France. His teaching positions brought him from Lille, then briefly to Rennes, then to Bordeaux for the remainder of his life, but never to Paris.

Duhem assumed the position of Maitre de Conférences at the Faculté des Sciences at Lille in October 1887. There he met Adèle Chayet, whom he married in October 1890. Their daughter Hélène was born in September 1891. Tragically, Adèle died in childbirth the following summer; the newborn child also did not survive. Duhem never remarried. He left the upbringing of Hélène to his mother who lived with him after his father Pierre-Joseph died. The situation in Lille soured for Duhem. Never one to back off from a dispute, he fought with the Dean of his faculty over a minor issue: an assistant had failed to unlock the door of Duhem’s laboratory for his students during their licentiate examinations. The assistant complained about his mistreatment by Duhem to the Dean, who requested that the assistant write a letter of apology; Duhem rejected the apology and took issue with the Dean, who then brought the matter to the Rector, adding further complaints against Duhem. The minor issue having escalated to immense proportions, Duhem requested and received a change of positions at the end of academic year 1893. During these formative years, Duhem worked very hard on his science. He published six books: a two-volume work on hydrodynamics, elasticity, and acoustics, his lectures on electricity and magnetism, in three volumes, and an introduction to physical chemistry. Duhem was one of the first to appreciate the work of W. J. Gibbs, writing the earliest critical examination of Gibbs’ “On the Equilibrium of Heterogeneous Substances” in 1887 and later promoting the French translation of Gibbs’ works (Duhem 1907); for an English translation of Duhem’s 1887 essay on Gibbs and his Commentaries on the Principles of Thermodynamics, 1892–1894, see Duhem [CPT].

In October 1893, Duhem left Lille for Rennes. He lasted only one year, leaving for Bordeaux in October 1894. He was hoping for a position in Paris. The prodigious quantity and quality of his publications in many fields of science, the philosophy of science, and the history of science were not able to change his situation. Very late in life, he was approached about the newly created chair in the History of Science at the Collège de France, but he refused to be a candidate for it. The proud and stubborn Duhem told his daughter: “I am a theoretical physicist. Either I will teach theoretical physics at Paris or else I will not go there.”

Duhem’s curriculum vitae, written in 1913, on the occasion of his nomination as non-resident member of the Académie des Sciences (1917, 41–70), lists over 350 items, about 50 of which were books. From the mid-1880s to 1900, Duhem’s primary interests were scientific, ranging from thermodynamics and physics, but publishing on elasticity and energetics as late as 1911. In the 1890s, while still at Lille, he began writing essays on questions of methodology that would lead to the publication of his most influential books in the philosophy of science, translated into English as The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory and To Save the Phenomena . It was also in the mid-1890s that Duhem published his first essays in the history of science, starting on the path that would lead him in 1904 to a new understanding of the history of science and to his thesis of continuity between medieval and early modern science. This path would culminate in such important historical works as Études sur Léonard de Vinci and Le système du monde .

Duhem made a number of enduring contributions to thermodynamics and physical chemistry. Among these were the Duhem–Margules and Gibbs–Duhem equations, which deal with reversible processes in thermodynamics as quasi-static limiting processes and give a general proof of the Gibbs phase rule. These results were obtained in the context of a program of generalized thermodynamics called “energetics.” Indeed, Duhem’s entire scientific program was driven by the conviction that a generalized thermodynamics should be foundational for physical theory, thinking that all of chemistry and physics, including mechanics, electricity and magnetism, should be derivable from thermodynamic first principles. Duhem started from the concept of the thermodynamic potential (the topic of his failed thesis), deploying it in a manner similar to that of potentials in mechanics, so as to represent all physical and chemical changes. The program finds its mature statement in his Traité d’énergétique of 1911; it was well received by late-nineteenth-century energeticists, such as Wilhelm Ostwald and Georg Helm. So important was energetics for Duhem, that his work in the history and philosophy of science has been viewed as an attempt to defend its aims and methods (see Lowinger 1941). More recently, Niall Martin and others have argued for the importance of religious motives in Duhem’s work (see Martin 1991, Jaki 1991) and it has become clear in the course of Duhem’s writings that he expected the endpoint of science to harmonize with the teachings of the Catholic Church.

Whatever was Duhem’s initial motivation, his historical and philosophical work took on a life of its own. One cannot read Duhem’s numerous historical and philosophical tomes and think that his labor was only in the service of energetics and that the sole goal of his works was but a defense of its methods and its historical position. No doubt energetics might be a thread running through Duhem’s various works, and no doubt these works harmonize with the method of energetics as he conceives it, but energetics cannot be the whole story.

2. Philosophy of Science

Duhem’s early methodological views reflected late nineteenth-century positivism: Physical theory was no more than an aid to memory, summarizing and classifying facts by providing a symbolic representation of them; the facts of physical theory are different from common sense and metaphysics, especially from the mechanical theories fashionable at the time. Duhem’s position was immediately attacked by a Catholic engineer, Eugène Vicaire, on the grounds that separating physics from metaphysics implied that physics was the only real knowledge (another positivistic thesis), and thus conceded too much to skepticism. Vicaire raised an important point for turn-of-the-century Catholics because the Church was officially committed to neo-Thomism, with its generally rationalist apologetics (see Martin 1991, chap. 2). In his reply Duhem adopted a quasi-Thomist position: metaphysics is a real form of knowledge, more excellent than physics, but separated from it in that it has different objects and is governed by different methods. This immediate response fitted reasonably well into the framework of neo-Thomism, though it did not go as far as to reunite the disparate forms of knowledge into a hierarchical system of sciences including cosmology and metaphysics. Duhem’s mature position was somewhat different, containing three key ideas elaborated upon on various occasions: (1) the underdetermination of theory by fact, often referred to as the Duhem Thesis, (2) the rejection of metaphysics and models in physics, and (3) natural classification as the endpoint of physical theory.

Duhem’s work was important for members of the Vienna Circle, including Otto Neurath and Philipp Frank, as it had been for Ernst Mach (for a comparison between Duhem and Mach on thought experiments and conventionalism, see Buzzoni 2015). Despite Duhem’s conservative beliefs, his work was also taken up by participants in the Viennese political scene, such as Friedrich Adler, who had translated La théorie physique into German in 1908. The Duhem thesis surfaced fully in Anglo-American philosophy in the 1950s through the work of W. V. O. Quine. In Quine’s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” the second dogma is reductionism, the belief that “each meaningful statement is equivalent to some construct upon terms which refer to immediate experience” (1953, 20). Quine argues that reductionism is an ill-founded dogma. He asserts that although reductionism has ceased to figure in some empiricists’ thoughts, there remains a more subtle form of reductionism that each statement taken in isolation can admit confirmation or disconfirmation. Against this dogma Quine suggests that “our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually, but only as a corporate body” (1953, 41), and, in a footnote of the reprinted article in his collected essays, From a Logical Point of View , says that the doctrine was well argued by Pierre Duhem. Quine proceeds to detail an “empiricism without the dogmas” in which knowledge is to be likened to a field of force where “a conflict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the field” (1953, 42), and “any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system” (1953, 43). Because of Quine’s reference to Duhem, the thesis formed from the two sub-theses, that (i) since empirical statements are interconnected, they cannot be singly disconfirmed, and (ii), if we wish to hold a particular statement true we can always adjust another statement, has become known as the Duhem-Quine thesis.The antecedent of sub-thesis (i) is often referred to as “holism.” Quine attributes only sub-thesis (i) to Duhem; Duhem would have recognized sub-thesis (i) as an offspring of his, but would not have fully agreed with it as formulated by Quine.

Duhem does not claim that when there is some conflict with experience, we can always make enough adjustments elsewhere in the system. He makes a weaker claim, also limited in other ways, but which would be equivalent to: when there is some conflict with experience what is disconfirmed is necessarily ambiguous. Duhem’s formulation of his non-falsifiability thesis is that “if the predicted phenomenon is not produced, not only is the questioned proposition put into doubt, but also the whole theoretical scaffolding used by the physicist” (1914, 281; 1954, 185). He does not take the second Quinean step of holding any statement true come what may, but says “the only thing the experiment teaches us is that, among all the propositions used to predict the phenomenon and to verify that it has not been produced, there is at least one error; but where the error lies is just what the experiment does not tell us” (1914, 281; 1954, 185). He refers to two possible ways of proceeding when an experiment contradicts the consequences of a theory: a timid scientist might wish to safeguard certain fundamental hypotheses and attempt to complicate matters by invoking various cases of error and multiplying the corrections, while a bolder scientist can resolve to change some of the essential suppositions supporting the entire system (1914, 329; 1954, 216–17). The scientist has no guarantee of success: “If they both succeed in satisfying the requirements of the experiment, each is logically permitted to declare himself content with the work he has accomplished” (1914, 330; 1954, 217).

Moreover, Duhem does not argue directly for the non-falsifiability thesis. He seems to regard it as an obvious corollary of another thesis, which could be called the non-separability thesis, that the physicist can never submit an isolated hypothesis to experimental test: “To seek to separate each of the hypotheses of theoretical physics from the other assumptions upon which this science rests, in order to subject it in isolation to the control of observation, is to pursue a chimera” (1914, 303; 1954, 199–200).

The Duhemian thesis usually makes its appearance in the context of Duhem’s critique of the inductive method (or what he calls the Newtonian method), which rejects any hypothesis about imperceptible bodies and hidden movements and admits only general laws known by induction from observation. Duhem accuses this method of being unmanageable; he asserts that a science can only follow the Newtonian method when its means of knowing are those of common sense: “When science no longer observes facts directly but substitutes for them measurements, given by instruments, of magnitudes that mathematical theory alone defines, induction can no longer be practiced in the manner that the Newtonian method requires,” (1917, 153; [EHPS, 234]). He clearly indicates that some sciences can use the Newtonian method, derive their principles by induction from observation and disconfirm them as tests warrant. What Duhem thinks is wrong with inductivism is that it cannot be used by all sciences. For Duhem the non-falsifiability thesis is a consequence of the non-separability thesis, and the non-separability thesis is an empirical thesis depending upon factors that do not govern all sciences. This is supported as well by Duhem’s assertions, in La théorie physique , that he is imposing narrow limits on his inquiry, and is restricting his generalizations to physics; when he first announces the non-separability thesis, he announces it as a principle about what physicists do, whose consequences will be developed in the remainder of the book.

It is not generally known that Duhem in his lifetime confronted an extension of his thesis in the fashion of Quine and had previously rejected it. In the 1913 essay entitled “Examen logique de la théorie physique,” republished as part II of the overview of all his work, Duhem sketched the set of theses constituting the Duhem thesis and stated:

Separated from the various schools of Pragmatists on the subject of the value of physical theory, we do not take our stand, in any circumstance, among the number of their followers. The analysis we have given of experiments in physics shows fact to be completely interpenetrated by theoretical interpretation, to the point where it becomes impossible to express fact in isolation from theory, in such experiments. This analysis has found great favor on the side of many Pragmatists. They have extended it to the most diverse fields: to history, to exegesis, to theology. (1917, 156 [EHPS, 237])

Thus, already by 1913, the scope of Duhem’s thesis had been stretched beyond Duhem’s intentions. “The several authors we have just cited often draw from this analysis of the experimental method used in physics conclusions which go beyond the boundaries of physics; we shall not follow them that far, but shall stay always within the limits of physical science” (1914, 218n; 1954, 144n). While Duhem did not identify these authors, these “pragmatists,” as early as 1905, in a footnote of La théorie physique , he asserts that some of his friends and acquaintances and, in particular, Gaston Milhaud, Edouard Le Roy, and Joseph Wilbois had adopted his analysis of experimental method, as discussed in his earlier articles (1914, 217–218n; 1954, 144n). And these same thinkers, together with Duhem’s very good friend, Maurice Blondel, were referred to favorably as “French pragmatists” by William James in 1907 in his Lectures on Pragmatism : “If my lectures interest any reader in the general subject, he will doubtless wish to read farther. I therefore give him a few references. … Furthermore, see J. Milhaud, Le Rationnel , 1898, and the fine articles by Le Roy in the Revue de Metaphysique , vols. 7, 8, and 9. Also articles by Blondel and de Sailly in the Annales de Philosophie Chrétienne , 4eme Série, vols. 2 and 3. Papini announces a book on Pragmatism, in the French language, to be published very soon” (James, 1981, 3; a quick glance at Milhaud’s Le Rationnel reveals numerous references to Duhem). Thus the Duhem thesis in its extended form was favorably received in the Anglophone world during the first few decades of the twentieth century, well before Quine’s reference to it. Duhem’s reaction to the extension of his thesis was as follows:

We do not deny that this extension is legitimate to some extent. However different the problems may be, it is always the same human intellect that exerts itself to resolve them. In the same way, there is always something common in the several procedures reason employs. But if it is good to notice the analogies between our diverse scientific methods, it is on condition that we do not forget the differences separating them. And, when we compare the method of physics, so strangely specialized in the application of mathematical theory and by the use of measuring instruments, to other methods, there are surely more differences to describe than analogies to discover. (1917, 156 [EHPS, 237])

In the overview of all his scholarly works in the document supporting his candidacy for membership to the Académie des Sciences Duhem contrasted the methodology of energetics with the two leading methodologies at the time, what he called the method of the Cartesians and that of the Newtonians. We have discussed his critique of the Newtonians; we now turn to that of the Cartesians. The salient feature of energetics was that “the principles it embodies and from which it derives conclusions do not at all aspire to resolve the bodies we perceive or the motions we report into imperceptible bodies or hidden motions” (1917, 151 [EHPS, 232]). What energetics offered was a formal theory, with the character of logical system, which instead of reducing physical qualities in the manner of mechanistic theories, limited itself to marking by means of a numerical scale the various intensities of such qualities. Duhem’s critique of mechanistic theories (or the method of Cartesians and atomists) was that they are not autonomous:

The physicist who wishes to follow them can no longer use the methods proper to physics exclusively. … Here he enters the domain of cosmology. He no longer has the right to shut his ears to what metaphysics wishes to tell him about the real nature of matter; hence, as a consequence, through dependence on metaphysical cosmology, his physics suffers from all the uncertainties and vicissitudes of that doctrine. Theories constructed by the method of the Cartesians and atomists are also condemned to infinite multiplication and to perpetual reformulation. They do not appear to be in any state to assure consensus and continual progress to science. (1917, 152 [EHPS, 233–34])

For Duhem, the contemporary scientist who exemplified the method of the “Cartesians” was James Clerk Maxwell. Duhem issued three interconnected complaints against Maxwell’s work: (i) Maxwell’s theory is overly bold or not systematic enough; (ii) it is too dependent on models; and (iii) its concepts are not continuous with those of the past.

The justification Duhem gives for the accusation of extreme boldness is that:

When a physicist discovers facts unknown until then, when his experiments have allowed him to formulate new laws that the theory had not foreseen, he must first try with the greatest care to represent these laws, to the required degree of approximation, as consequences of admitted hypotheses. Only after having acquired the certainty that the magnitudes treated until now by the theory cannot serve as symbols for the observed quantities, that received hypotheses cannot flow from the established laws, is he authorized to enrich physics with a new magnitude, to complicate it with a new hypothesis (1902, 7).

According to Duhem, the founders of electrodynamics—Coulomb, Poisson, and Ampere—followed these principles, but Maxwell did not. Duhem cites with approbation Ampere’s attempt to represent the attraction or repulsion of currents in wires using Coulomb’s formula. He also praises the fact that Ampere abandoned the attempt only after experimental facts about the magneto-optical rotation, discovered by Faraday, showed clearly that Ampere could not succeed in the attempt. But, again, according to Duhem, Maxwell does not follow these principles. In fact, he goes so far as to accuse Maxwell of following the “inverse path”:

At the moment when Maxwell introduced a new magnitude in electrodynamics, the displacement currents, at the moment when he marked, as essential hypotheses, the mathematical form of the laws to which this magnitude should be submitted, no properly observed phenomenon required this extension of the theory of currents; that theory was sufficient for representing, if not all phenomena known until then, at least all those whose experimental study had achieved a sufficient degree of clearness. No logical necessity pressed Maxwell to imagine a new electrodynamics. (1902, 8.)

As a result, Maxwell reversed “with an incredible rashness” the natural order according to which physical theory evolves—he broke with the past before he needed to.

Duhem is well known for his attack on the use of models in physical science. At first, it seems that Duhem tries to link his attack on model building with his espousal of instrumentalism for the physical sciences. He accuses the English scientists of believing that “to understand physical phenomena is to compose a model” (1914, 103; 1954, 71–72) and of “confusing model with theory” (1913, 102; 1954, 71). He specifically blames Maxwell of these misunderstandings, indicating that in his 1855–56 essay Maxwell proposed only “to illustrate” the theory of dielectrics, whereas in his 1861–62 essay he proposed “to represent or to explain” the electrical and magnetic actions by a mechanical model. Duhem even seems scornful of Maxwell’s interchangeable use of the verbs “to represent” and “to explain.” He states, “for an English physicist, the two words have the same meaning” (1902, 9).

For Duhem there is a crucial difference between representing and explaining. He divides theories into two large categories, explanatory and purely representative theories, and argues that physical theories should not be considered as explanatory, but as purely representative or classificatory. The argument, as we have seen, is that, in order for physical theory to be explanatory, it would have to be subordinate to metaphysics and not autonomous. The reference to the two words having the same meaning for Maxwell and English scientists is thus a reference to what Duhem would consider a confusion about the aim of physical theory, one that arises in the identification of the model with the theory, in thinking that what is represented by the theory and/or model is real.

But Duhem broadens the critique of model building to include mathematical models along with mechanical models. He decides that, for an English scientist, theory is “for him neither an explanation nor a rational classification of physical laws, but a model of these laws, a model not built for the satisfying of reason but for the pleasure of the imagination” (1914, 117; 1954, 81). The complaint is clear: model building has no real place in physical theory (beyond a minor heuristic role); it can neither be grounded in realism, in the thought that physical theories are explanatory structures, nor in instrumentalism, in the thought that physical theories are classificatory or representative structures. In fact, model building is not even connected to the higher intellectual faculty of reason but to the lower faculty of imagination. So, ultimately, Duhem’s attack on model building is rooted in something more fundamental than his instrumentalist methodology for the physical sciences.

Duhem banishes model building from physical theory (as he previously banished Maxwell’s rashness) because model building breaks with historical continuity; in fact, model building is not only historically non-continuous, but present models are even often “non-continuous” among themselves. Some model builders even find pleasure in building two or more models of the same law. The fact that the English physicist can accept disparate models, breaking up the historical continuity of science and even its present unification, is what shocks Duhem; it is what reconfirms for him that English physics is not the work of reason, but the work of imagination.

A principle of historical continuity is invoked in the conclusion of Duhem’s primary work on Maxwell. Duhem evaluates there an interpretation of Maxwell’s work he attributes to Heaviside, Hertz, and Cohn, among others. He quotes Hertz as stating that: “what is essential in Maxwell’s theories is Maxwell’s equations.” He takes this to be Hertz’s way of salvaging what is valuable in Maxwell from the midst of logical errors and incoherence, which are not only difficult to correct, but which have frustrated many illustrious mathematicians. But Duhem cannot accept Hertz’s implied criterion of identity for physical theories. He asserts that he might accept such a criterion for algebra but “a physicist is not an algebraist”:

An equation does not simply bear on letters; such letters symbolize physical magnitudes which must be either measurable experimentally or formed from other measurable magnitudes. Therefore, if a physicist is given only an equation, he is not taught anything. To this equation must be joined rules by which the letters that the equation bears upon are made to correspond to the physical magnitudes they represent. And that which allows us to know these rules is the set of hypotheses and arguments by which one has arrived at the equations in question. [The set of rules] is the theory that the equations summarize in a symbolic form: in physics, an equation, detached from the theory that leads to it, has no meaning . (1902, 223.)

Duhem proceeds to detail two complete theories that can recover Maxwell’s equations within a logical and coherent structure, the theories of Boltzmann and Helmholtz. The only criterion he gives for choosing between these two theories, though without elaborating upon it or justifying it, is that Helmholtz’s theory is to be preferred over Boltzmann’s theory because it is a natural “extension of the doctrines of Poisson, Ampere, Weber, and Newmann; it leads logically from the principles posited at the start of the nineteenth century to the most seductive consequences of Maxwell’s theories, from the laws of Coulomb to the electromagnetic theory of light; [it does so] without losing any of the recent victories of electrical science; it reestablishes the continuity of tradition” (1902, 225).

Duhem does not attempt to justify his criterion of historical continuity in his study of Maxwell, perhaps because he previously broached the question. In an early methodological article, he asserts:

IF WE RESTRICT OURSELVES TO INVOKING CONSIDERATIONS OF PURE LOGIC, we cannot prevent a physicist from representing different sets of laws, or even a single group of laws, by several irreconcilable theories. We cannot condemn incoherence in the development of physical theory . (1893, 366 and elsewhere; [EHPS, 66])

Thus historical continuity as a consideration falls outside of pure logic and outside reasons of physics proper, but deals with the relation between physics and metaphysics, what Duhem calls “metaphysical cosmology.” Surprisingly, if one considers him as an instrumentalist, for Duhem, we must judge a physical theory in comparison to an ideal and perfect theory that provides the total and adequate metaphysical explanation of the nature of material things, that is, the natural classification of laws. (For more on Duhem on natural classification and conventionalism, see Dion 2013, Dion 2017, and Ivanova 2015.) For that reason, a coherent physical theory is more perfect than an incoherent set of incompatible theories. Elaborating upon this point and commenting upon the connection between cosmology—that is, metaphysics, natural classification, or the ideal form of physical theory—and physical theory itself, Duhem asserts:

It is not enough for cosmologists to know very accurately the doctrines of contemporary theoretical physics; they must also know past doctrines. In fact, current theory need not be analogous with cosmology, but with the ideal theory toward which current theory tends by a continual progress. Therefore, it is not up to philosophers to compare physics as it is now with their cosmology, by congealing science in some manner at a precise moment of its evolution, but rather to appreciate the development of theory and to surmise the goal toward which it is directed. Now, nothing can guide them safely in conjecturing the path that physics will follow if not the knowledge of the road it has already covered. (1914, 460; 1954, 303.)

Duhem supports this statement using an analogy with the trajectory of a ball. We cannot guess its end point with an instant glance at the ball, but we can prolong its trajectory if we followed the ball from the moment it was struck. So we cannot guess the end point of physical theory, the natural classification, by looking at any particular theory. We must appeal to the trajectory of physical theory, to its history, to enable us to tell whether any particular theory is likely to contribute toward the ultimate natural classification. Duhem’s doctrine of natural classification provides the grounds for various commentators to argue that Duhem is not an instrumentalist, that his philosophy of science considered as a whole looks more like convergent or motivational realism (see Maiocchi in Ariew and Barker 1990 and others).

As presented so far, Duhem is a philosopher who weaves together two large patchworks of theses: (i) instrumentalism or fictionalism, anti-atomism or anti-Cartesianism, anti-modelism, and autonomy of physics from metaphysics and (ii) anti-inductivism or critique of Newtonian method, the Duhem thesis, that is, non-falsifiability and non-separability. Both sets of theses are intended as empirical theses about the workings of science and both are important to understanding Duhem’s thought. The first set of theses effectively demarcates physical theory as an autonomous domain apart from other domains, that is, rejects any external method, and the second set then operates on the internal workings of physical theory. Having set apart physical theory, Duhem asserts that no internal method leads inexorably to the truth.

For Duhem, there are always at least two basic ways of proceeding in science. Some scientists prefer the clutter of concrete details and thus do not mind ad hoc explanations, complications, and corrected theories; others prefer abstract, simple, and uncomplicated theories, even if they are gotten at the price of conceptual novelty. As we have seen, Duhem discusses this dichotomy under the rubric of the English mind and the French mind—what he also calls “esprit de finesse” and “esprit de géométrie,” following Blaise Pascal. Despite the labels “English” and “French,” Duhem’s categories are analytic ones, not mere epithets to be used rhetorically against his adversaries. In fact, from the start, when he described the broad-shallow English mind, his archetype was Napoleon Bonaparte, a great genius of military details—not an Englishman. Duhem’s ideal of the narrow-deep French mind was Newton, the geometer of physics—not a Frenchman. Thus, when Duhem accused Faraday and Maxwell of having English minds, he did so by trying to establish something about how they conducted their science, not by referring to their ancestry.

In his last work, La science allemande , mostly a work of wartime propaganda, Duhem added a third kind of mind to his original two, namely, the German mind. If there are two basic types, the French mind and the English mind, then what could the German mind possibly be? Citing Pascal, Duhem tells us that truth requires both reason and argument— raison and raisonnement . Logic, or our ability to link propositions with one another, allows us to deduce one truth from another; but that ability, by itself, merely gets us back to first principles or axioms. We also need a faculty that allows us to intuit the truth of the first principles or axioms, that is, bon sens (good sense). Bon sens is to “esprit de finesse” what “pure logic” is to “esprit de géométrie.” Moreover, bon sens , our faculty of recognizing fundamental truth gets perfected by the practice of history, by our becoming more aware of the failures and successes of previous theories, by thinking about the trajectory of scientific theories, rather than by considering a single theory frozen in time. The dual scheme can now be expanded. We need logic, the ability to systematize, but we also need intuition, the recognition of truth. When one of these is allowed to dominate, we get a science which is all intuition, all “esprit de finesse,” but no logical coherence, namely, English science; or we get a science which is all logic, lacking bon sens, namely, German science. German science then is a degenerate kind of French science, the latter being predominantly “esprit de géométrie,” corrected by bon sens .

As a result, we can talk about a continuum of sciences; at one extreme on the theoretical side is German science, or logicism, and at the other extreme on the experimental side is English science, or crude modelism. In the middle is French science, which allegedly tempers the logical bent with historicism.

In a well-known chapter of Social Theory and Social Structure , the sociologist of science Robert Merton refers to Duhem’s critique of German science as one of the many polemics against national kinds affirming a universalistic standard: “Dispassionate scientists impugned ‘enemy’ contributions, charging nationalistic bias, log-rolling, intellectual dishonesty, incompetence, and lack of creative capacity. Yet this very deviation from the norm of universalism actually presupposed the legitimacy of the norm. For nationalistic bias is opprobrious only if judged in terms of the standard of universalism… Thus by the very process of condemning their violation, the mores are reaffirmed” (1968, 8).

At first glance Duhem’s polemics against German science might seem to arise from a universalistic standard. Duhem does talk at times of a perfect form of science, one without personal or national character: “Quite often the great masters possess a reason in which all the faculties are so harmoniously proportioned that their very perfect doctrines are exempt from all individual character, as from all national character. … In such works one no longer sees the genius of this or that people, but only the genius of Humanity” (1915, 105 [EHPS, 253]). Such perfection for Duhem is an equilibrium of disparate elements, not itself a single ideal type. Duhem might regret what he sees as an overabundance of esprit de géométrie in German science, and might wish that it be tempered by a bit more finesse, but there is no suggestion in Duhem that there is only one way to proceed in science.

Duhem specifically states that the

perfect form of science could not be obtained except by a very precise separation of the various methods concurring in the discovery of truth. Each of the many faculties that human reason puts into play when it wishes to know more and better would have to play its role, without anything being omitted, without any faculty being overlooked. This perfect equilibrium between the many organs of reason does not occur in any one man. In each of us one faculty is stronger and another weaker. In the conquest of truth the weaker will not contribute as much as it should and the stronger will take on more than its share. (1915, 104 [EHPS, 252]).

At bottom, despite his talk of ideal type and equilibrium, Duhem’s science is not universalistic. The strength of his analysis is that there is no single direction within science that each individual must follow. For that, one would need to ground physics in a particular metaphysics—which Duhem explicitly rejects with his instrumentalism—or rather, to be guided by what one projects metaphysics will look like over the long run. Unfortunately, Duhem took this last thought too rigidly and ultimately condemned all innovations as breaking with the past, either due to an excess of esprit de géométrie , as with non-Euclidean geometry and relativity, or an excess of esprit de finesse , as with electron theory. But his philosophy of science itself contained the seeds of scientific pluralism, which are the foundations of the Duhem thesis, that is, the thought that there are many legitimate and disparate ways of proceeding in science.

Duhem’s famous critique of crucial experiments follows a similar pattern. Duhem argues that crucial experiments resemble false dilemmas: hypotheses in physics do not come in pairs, so that crucial experiments cannot transform one of the two into a demonstrated truth. For example, the Newtonian emission theory predicts that light travels faster in water than in air; according to the wave theory, light travels slower in water than in air. Dominique François Arago proposed a crucial experiment comparing the respective velocities. Léon Foucault then devised an apparatus to measure the speed of light in various media and found a lower velocity in water than in air. Arago and Foucault concluded for the wave theory, thinking that the experiment refuted the emission theory. Discussing Foucault’s experiment, Duhem asks whether we dare assert that no other hypothesis is imaginable and suggests that instead of light being either a simple particle or wave, it might be something else, perhaps a disturbance propagated within a dielectric medium, as theorized by Maxwell (1914, 285–89; 1954, 188–90).

More than a century after Duhem argued for his non-falsifiability thesis, the set of issues connected with it are still elaborated upon, criticized, and defended in the large literature on the philosophy of science. Given holism, non-falsifiability follows logically and thus, when an experiment goes wrong, there is no set way to determine which hypothesis among many hypotheses is defective. Duhem proposed bon sens as a resolution to the problem, but that solution seemed unsatisfactory to many: it looked more psychological than epistemological and it sounded too vague. Thus scholars attempted to articulate further what Duhem might have meant as bon sens (see Ivanova 2010, Kidd 2011, Ivanova 2011, and Ivanova and Pasternote 2013). Others proposed their own resolutions to the problem, attempting to isolate defective hypotheses by extra-logical means, whether by inference to the best explanation, Bayesian devices, error-statistical methods, or though elaborate experimental practices; for an analysis of such solutions, see Dietrich and Honenberger 2020 or Ivanova 2021).

For most of the nineteenth century, scholars treated “medieval science” as an oxymoron. Since nothing from the Middle Ages was worthy of the name “science,” no history of medieval science could be written. For example, William Whewell referred to Greek philosophy as “the period of the first waking of science” and to the medieval era as “that of its mid-day slumber” (1857, I, Introduction). As a result, Whewell’s chapter on medieval science from the History of the Inductive Sciences , entitled “Of the Mysticism of the Middle Ages,” was just two-pages long.

With work such as Whewell’s being typical of Duhem’s intellectual context, when Duhem wrote L’évolution de la mécanique , in 1903, he dismissed the Middle Ages as scientifically sterile. Similarly, Duhem’s history of chemical combination, Le mixte et la combinaison chimique , published in book-form in 1902, had jumped from Aristotle’s concept of mixtio to modern concepts. It was only in 1904, while writing Les origines de la statique that Duhem came across an unusual reference to a then-unknown medieval thinker, Jordanus de Nemore. His pursuit of this reference, and the research to which it led, is widely acknowledged to have created the field of the history of medieval science. Where Duhem’s previous histories had been silent, Les origines de la statique contained a number of chapters on medieval science: one treated Jordanus de Nemore; another treated his followers; a third argued their influence on Leonardo de Vinci. In the second volume, Duhem greatly extended his historical scope. As expected, he covered seventeenth-century statics, but he also returned to the middle ages, spending four chapters on geostatics, including the work of Albert of Saxony in the fourteenth century. Les origines de la statique is thus a transition from Duhem’s early conventional histories to the later work for which he is best known, Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci , and Le Système du monde , in which his thesis of the continuity of late medieval and early modern science is fully displayed.

From 1906 to 1913, Duhem delved deeply into his favorite guide for the recovery of the past, the scientific notebooks of Leonardo de Vinci. He published a series of essays uncovering de Vinci’s medieval sources and their influences on the moderns. The third volume of Duhem’s Etudes sur Léonard de Vinci gained a new subtitle, Les précurseurs parisiens de Galilée, announcing Duhem’s bold new thesis that even the works of Galileo had a medieval heritage; reviewing his historical accomplishments, Duhem summarized them as follows:

When we see the science of Galileo triumph over the stubborn Peripatetic philosophy of somebody like Cremonini, we believe, since we are ill-informed about the history of human thought, that we are witness to the victory of modern, young science over medieval philosophy, so obstinate in its mechanical repetition. In truth, we are contemplating the well-paved triumph of the science born at Paris during the fourteenth century over the doctrines of Aristotle and Averroes, restored into repute by the Italian Renaissance. (1917, 162 [EHPS, 193])

Duhem presented Galilean dynamics as a continuous development out of medieval dynamics. He recovered the late medieval theory of impetus, tracing it from John Philoponus’ criticism of Aristotle to its mature statements in the fourteenth century works of John Buridan and Nicole Oresme: “The role that impetus played in Buridan’s dynamics is exactly the one that Galileo attributed to impeto or momento , Descartes to ‘quantity of motion,’ and Leibniz finally to vis viva . So exact is this correspondence that, in order to exhibit Galileo’s dynamics, Torricelli, in his Lezioni accademiche , often took up Buridan’s reasons and almost his exact words” (1917, 163–62 [EHPS, 194]). Duhem then sketched the extension of impetus theory from terrestrial dynamics to the motions of the heavens and earth:

Nicole Oresme attributed to the earth a natural impetus similar to the one Buridan attributed to the celestial orbs. In order to account for the vertical fall of weights, he allowed that one must compose this impetus by which the mobile rotates around the earth with the impetus engendered by weight. The principle he distinctly formulated was only obscurely indicated by Copernicus and merely repeated by Giordano Bruno. Galileo used geometry to derive the consequences of that principle, but without correcting the incorrect form of the law of inertia implied in it. (1917, 166 [EHPS, 196])

Duhem’s essays on Leonardo de Vinci concluded with a speculation about the means for the transmission of medieval ideas to modern science. Since the studies of Buridan and Oresme had remained in large part in manuscript, Duhem suggested that Albert of Saxony, whose works were printed and reprinted during the sixteenth century, was the likely link to Galileo. Duhem’s key to understanding the transmission of medieval science was Galileo’s use of the phrase Doctores Parisienses , a conventional label denoting Buridan and Oresme, among others. Based on evidence including references to certain unusual doctrines and the particular order in which the questions were arranged, Duhem conjectured that Galileo had consulted George Lokert’s compilation of Albert of Saxony, Themo Judaeus, and others, and the works of the Dominican Domingo de Soto (1906–13, III.582–83). Duhem’s conjecture has been revised and expanded upon: The means of transmission has been made clearer because of the labor of A. C. Crombie, Adriano Carugo, and William Wallace.

In the three years before his death in 1916, Duhem wrote Le Système du monde , but did not succeed in finishing it. He intended it as a twelve-volume work on the history of cosmological doctrines, ending with Copernicus. He completed nine volumes, the first five being published from 1914 to 1919, and the next four having to wait until the 1950s; a tenth, incomplete volume was also published then. These tomes impart an enormous amount of information about medieval astronomy, astrology, tidal theory, and geostatics, again presenting many sources for the first time in the modern era. They also trace developments in doctrines associated with such concepts as infinity, place, time, void, and the plurality or unity of the world. Duhem intended to write a 300-page summary of his results after he was done with the Le Système du monde ; he did not have the time to accomplish what would have surely been an amazing volume. (Duhem [LAS] is an attempt to construct such a single volume from the ten volumes of the Le Système du monde .)

Unlike his philosophical work, Duhem’s influential contemporaries did not receive his historical work with sympathy. As early as 1916, Antonio Favaro, the editor of Le Opere di Galileo Galilei , rejected the continuity of medieval and early modern science. The next generation of historians of science, Alexandre Koyré for example, acknowledged Duhem’s studies as the foundation for modern studies of medieval science, but subjected them to harsh criticism. Two themes divide Koyré’s historical work from that of Duhem. It presents histories of science in which metaphysics plays a primary role in explaining scientific change and it espouses a historiography that gives a central place to the concept of revolution. Medieval thought and early modern science are judged to be different in kind as well as in content.

At the beginning of an essay on void and infinite space, Koyré quotes a passage from Duhem that has become infamous: “If we were obliged to assign a date to the birth of modern science, we would undoubtedly choose 1277, when the Bishop of Paris solemnly proclaimed that a multiplicity of worlds could exist, and that the system of celestial spheres could, without contradiction, be endowed with straight line motion” (1906–13, II.411; see also 1913–59, VII. 4). Koyré calls the two theses from the condemnations of 1277 “absurdities,” noting that they arise in a theological context, and rejects Duhem’s date for the birth of modern science; he remarks that Duhem gives another date elsewhere, corresponding to Buridan’s impetus theory being extended to the heavens, but dismisses it also, saying that “it is as false as the first date” (1961, 37n). For Koyré, the introduction of Platonic metaphysics, the mathematization of nature, marks a break with the Aristotelian Middle Ages.

Koyré’s work influenced Thomas Kuhn and others who made “scientific revolutions” a central feature of their historical accounts. Still, the work of Kuhn and later historically oriented philosophers and sociologists of science did attempt to reintegrate the philosophical and historical studies that Duhem pursued together but that were separated for a good part of the twentieth century.

Duhem often first published his main works, such as Les théories électriques de J. Clerk Maxwell , L’évolution de la mécanique , Les origines de la statique , La théorie physique , son objet et sa structure , serially as articles in such journals as Annales de la de la Société scientifique de Bruxelles , Revue Générale des Sciences pures et appliquées , Revue des Questions Scientifiques , Revue de Philosophie , respectively.

1886 , Paris: Hermann.
1892 “Quelques réflexions au sujet des théories physiques,” , 31: 139–177. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1892 “Notation atomique et hypothèses atomistiques,” , 31: 391–454.
1893 “Physique et métaphysique,” , 34: 55–83. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1893 “L’école anglaise et les théories physiques,” , 34: 345–78. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1894 “Quelques réflexions au sujet de la physique expérimentale,” , 36: 179–229. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1895 “Les théories de la chaleur” (in 3 parts), , 129: 869–901, 130: 379–415 and 851–68.
1896 “L’évolution des théories physiques du XVIIe siècle jusqu’à nos jours:” (2nd series), 40: 463–99.
1902 , Paris: Hermann. English translation, Alan Aversa, , Dordrecht: Springer, 2015.
1902 , Paris: C. Naud; 2nd. ed., Paris: Fayard, 1985. English translation, Paul Needham, , Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2002.
1902 , Paris, Gauthier-Villars. English translation, George K. Burgess, , New York: Wiley, 1903.
1903 , Paris: A. Joanin. German translation, P. Frank, , Leipzig: J.A. Barth, 1912. English translation, Michael Cole, , Alphen aan den Rijn: Sijthooff and Noordhoff, 1980.
1903 “Analyse de l’ouvrage de Ernst Mach,” , 27: 261–83. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1905 “Physique de croyant,” , 151: 44–67. Republished as an appendix of Duhem 1914.
1905–06 , 2 vols., Paris: Hermann. English Translation Grant F. Leneaux, Victor N. Vagliente, and Guy H. Wagener, , Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991.
1906 , Paris: Chevalier et Rivière. German Translation Friedrich Adler, , Leipzig: J.A. Barth, 1908.
1906 , Paris: Gauthier-Villars.
1907 , Paris: A. Hermann.
1908 , Paris: Hermann. English Translation Edmond Dolland and Chaninah Maschler, , Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969.
1906–13 , 3 vols., Paris: Hermann.
1911 “History of Physics,” , New York: R. Appleton, pp. 47–67. Reprinted in Duhem [EHPS].
1911 , 2 vols., Paris: Gauthier-Villars.
1912 “La nature du raisonnement mathématique,” , 12: 531–543. English translation in Duhem [EHPS].
1913–59 , 10 vols, Paris: Hermann.
1914 , 2nd ed., Paris: Chevalier et Rivière. English Translation Philip P. Wiener, , Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954.
1915 , Paris: Hermann. English translation John Lyon, , La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1991.
1916 Paris: Hermann.
1917 “Liste des Publications de P. Duhem” and “Notice sur les travaux scientifiques de Duhem,” , 7: 41–169. English translation of Parts 2 and 3 of “Notice” in Duhem [EHPS].
[MC] , Roger Ariew (trans.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985; partial translation of vols. 7–9 of .
[LPD] , Stanley L. Jaki (ed.), Paris: Beauchesne, 1994.
[EHPS] , ed. and translation with Introduction by Roger Ariew and Peter Barker, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996.
[LAS] , Anastasios Brenner (ed.), Paris: Hermann, 1997; selections from Duhem 1913–59.
[CPT] , ed. and trans. by Paul Needham, Cham: Springer, 2011.
  • Ariew, Roger, 1984, “The Duhem Thesis,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , 35: 313–25.
  • Ariew, Roger and Peter Barker, 1986, “Duhem on Maxwell: a Case-Study in the Interrelations of History of Science and Philosophy of Science,” Philosophy of Science Association , 1: 145–56.
  • Ariew, Roger and Peter Barker (eds.), 1990, Pierre Duhem: Historian and Philosopher of Science , Synthese , 83 (2) and (3).
  • Biard, Joel, 2004, “Le rôle des condamnations de 1277 dans le développement de la physique selon Pierre Duhem,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 15–36
  • Brenner, Anastasios, 1990, Duhem, Science, Réalité et Apparence , Paris: Vrin.
  • –––, 2004, “Genèse, évolution et continuité du développement scientifique selon Pierre Duhem,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 37–58.
  • Brenner, Anastasios (ed.), 1992, Pierre Duhem , Revue Internationale de Philosophie , 46.
  • Brenner, Anastasios, Paul Needham, David Stump, and Robert Deltete, 2011, “New perspectives on Pierre Duhem’s The aim and structure of physical theory ,” (Book Symposium), Metascience , 20: 1–25.
  • Brouzeng, Paul, 1979, “L’histoire des sciences dans l’élaboration et la diffusion de la connaissance scientifique chez Pierre Duhem,” Actes du 104e Congrès national des sociétés savantes de Bordeaux , Paris, pp. 159–167.
  • –––, 1987, Duhem, Science et Providence , Paris: Belin.
  • Buzzoni, Marco, 2018, “ Pierre Duhem and Ernst Mach on Thought Experiments,” HOPOS , 8: 1–27.
  • Darling, Karen M., 2002, “The Complete Duhemian Underdetermination Argument: Scientific Language and Practice,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 511–533.
  • –––, 2003, “Motivational Realism: The Natural Classification for Pierre Duhem,” Philosophy of Science , 70 (5): 1125–1136.
  • Dietrich, Michael, and Phillip Honenberger, 2020, “Duhem’s problem revisited: Logical vs epistemic formulations and solutions,” Synthese , 197: 337–54.
  • Dion, Sonia Maria, 2013, “Pierre Duhem and the inconsistency between instrumentalism and natural classification,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 44: 12–19.
  • –––, 2018, “Natural classification and Pierre Duhem’s historical work: Which relationships?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 69: 34–39.
  • Goddu, André, 1991, “Natural Classification: Pierre Duhem’s Continuity Thesis and the Resolution of Positivism, ” Historia philosophiae medii aevi , 1 (2): 329–348.
  • Hadamard, Jaques, 1927, “L’oeuvre de Duhem dans son aspect mathématique,” Mémoires de la Société des Sciences Physiques et naturelles de Bordeaux , 1: 635–665.
  • Harding, Sandra G., ed., 1976, Can Theories be Refuted? Essays on the Duhem-Quine Thesis , Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Ivanova, Milena, 2010, “Pierre Duhem’s good sense as a guide to theory choice,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 41: 58–64.
  • –––, 2011, “‘Good Sense’ in context: A response to Kidd,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 42: 610–12.
  • –––, 2015, “Conventionalism about what? Where Duhem and Poincaré part ways,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 54: 80–9.
  • –––, 2021, Duhem and Holism (Series: Cambridge Elements in the Philosophy of Science), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ivanova, Milena, and Cedric Paternote, 2013, “Theory Choice, Good Sense and Social Consensus,” Erkenntnis , 78: 1109–1132.
  • Jaki, Stanley L., 1984, Uneasy Genius, the Life and Work of Pierre Duhem , The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • –––, 1988, The Physicist as Artist: the landscapes of Pierre Duhem , Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
  • –––, 1991, Scientist and Catholic: an essay on Pierre Duhem , Front Royal, VA: Christendom Press; pp. 147–278 consist of English translation of selected texts from Duhem.
  • –––, 1992, Reluctant Heroine the Life and Work of Hélène Duhem , Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
  • James, William, 1981, Pragmatism , Indianapolis IN: Hackett.
  • Jordan, Emile, 1917, “Duhem, Pierre, Mémoires,” Société des Sciences Physiques et Naturelles de Bordeaux , 7 (1), 3–40.
  • Kidd, Ian James, 2011, “Pierre Duhem’s epistemic aims and the intellectual virtue of humility: A reply to Ivanova,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 42: 185–9.
  • Koyré, Alexandre, 1961, “Le vide et l’espace infini au XIVe siècle,” Etudes de l’histoire de la pensée philosophique , Paris: Gallimard. The essay was originally published in 1949.
  • Kragh, Helge, 2008, “Pierre Duhem, Entropy, and Christian Faith,” Physics in Perspective , 10: 379–95.
  • Lejbowicz, Max, 2004, “Pierre Duhem et l’histoire des sciences arabes,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 59–84.
  • Lowinger, Armand, 1941, The Methodology of Pierre Duhem , New York: Columbia.
  • Maiocchi, Roberto, 1985, Chimica e Filosofia, Scienza, epistemologia, storia e religione nell’Opera di Pierre Duhem , Firenze: La Nuova Italia.
  • Manville, Octave, 1928, L’oeuvre scientifique de Pierre Duhem , Paris: Blanchard.
  • Martin, R. N. D., 1976, “The Genesis of a Mediaeval Historian: Pierre Duhem and the Origins of Statics,” Annals of Science , 33: 119–129.
  • –––, 1982, “Saving Duhem and Galileo,” History of Science , 25: 302–319.
  • –––, 1991, Pierre Duhem: Philosophy and History in the Work of a Believing Physicist , La Salle, IL: Open Court.
  • –––, 1991, “The Trouble with Authority: the Galileo Affair and one of its Historians,” Modern Theology , 7: 269–80.
  • Mazauric, Simone, 2004, “Duhem et les lumières,” Revue des questions scientifiques , 175 (1): 85–104.
  • Merton, Robert, 1968, “Science and Democratic Social Structure,” Social Theory and Social Structure , New York: Free Press.
  • Miller, Donald G., 1970, “Pierre Duhem,” in Charles Gillispie, ed., Dictionary of Scientific Biography , New York: Scribner and American Council of Learned Societies, vol. 3, pp. 225–233.
  • Needham, Paul, 1996a, “Aristotelian Chemistry: A Prelude to Duhemian Metaphysics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , 26: 251–269.
  • –––, 1996b, “Substitution: Duhem’s Explication of a Chemical Paradigm,” Perspectives on Science , 4: 408–33.
  • –––, 1998, “Duhem’s Physicalism,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 29: 33–62.
  • –––, 2000, “Duhem and Quine,” Dialectica , 54: 109–132.
  • –––, 2002, “Duhem’s Theory of Mixture in the Light of the Stoic Challenge to the Aristotelian Conception,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 685–708.
  • –––, 2008, “Resisting Chemical Atomism: Duhem’s Argument,” Philosophy of Science , 75: 921–931.
  • Nye, Mary Jo, 1986, Science in the provinces: scientific communities and provincial leadership in France, 1860–1930 , Berkeley: University of California Press,
  • Patapievici, Horia-Roman, 2015, “The ‘Pierre Duhem thesis’: A reappraisal of Duhem’s discovery of the physics of the middle ages,” Logos & Episteme: An International Journal of Epistemology , 6: 201–218.
  • Paul, Harry W., 1979, The Edge of Contingency, French Catholic Reaction to Scientific Change from Darwin to Duhem , Gainesville: University Presses of Florida.
  • Pierre-Duhem, Helene, 1936, Un Savant Français, Pierre Duhem , Paris: Plon.
  • Quine, W. V. O., 1953, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” From a Logical Point of View , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. First version of the paper, without any reference to Duhem, in The Philosophical Review , 60 (1951): 20–53.
  • Stoffel, Jean-François, 1995, “L’histoire des théories physiques dans l’oeuvre de Pierre Duhem (avec une bibliographie exhaustive de la littérature consacrée à Duhem),” Sciences et techniques en perspective , Nantes, pp. 49–85.
  • –––, 1996, Pierre Duhem et ses doctorants: bibliographie de la littérature primaire et secondaire , Turnhout: Brepols.
  • –––, 2002, Le phénoménalisme problématique de Pierre Duhem , Brussels: Académie royale de Belgique.
  • Whewell, William, 1857, History of the Inductive Sciences , third edition (new impression with index), London: Cass, 1967.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Electronic text of Duhem’s La théorie physique, son objet, sa structure (1906)]
  • Electronic links to several of the articles in the 1911 Catholic Encyclopedia by Duhem: “History of Physics,” “Pierre de Maricourt,” “Jordanus de Nemore,” “Nicole Oresme,” “Albert of Saxony,” “Thierry of Freburg,” and “Jean de Sax.” Also included are links to Duhem’s “Physics of a Believer,” and a few other excerpts.

Albert of Saxony | analytic/synthetic distinction | atomism: 17th to 20th century | Bacon, Roger | Buridan, John [Jean] | condemnation of 1277 | Einstein, Albert: philosophy of science | fictionalism | Galileo Galilei | James, William | Kuhn, Thomas | logic: inductive | Mach, Ernst | Pascal, Blaise | physics: experiment in | Poincaré, Henri | Quine, Willard Van Orman | scientific progress | statistical physics: philosophy of statistical mechanics | thought experiments | underdetermination, of scientific theories | Vienna Circle | Whewell, William

Copyright © 2022 by Roger Ariew < rariew @ usf . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and Inference to the Best Explanation

Profile image of Marcel Weber

2009, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science

Related Papers

Miguel Flach

crucial experiment definition

Marcel Weber

Mauricio Suárez

On a purely epistemic understanding of experimental realism, manipulation affords a particularly robust kind of causal warrant, which is–like any other warrant–defeasible. I defend a version of Nancy Cartwright's inference to the most likely cause, and I conclude that this minimally epistemic version of experimental realism is a coherent, adequate and plausible epistemology for science.

Igor Douven

Philosophy of Science

Karen R Zwier

The manipulationist account of causation provides a framework for assessing causal claims and the experiments used to test them. But its pertinence to the more general class of scientific experiments—particularly those experiments not explicitly designed for testing causal claims—is less clear. I aim to show (1) that the set of causal inferences afforded by any experiment is determined solely on the basis of contrasting case structures that I call “experimental series” and (2) that the conditions that suffice for causal inference obtain quite commonly, even among “ordinary” scientific experiments not explicitly designed for the testing of causal claims.

Konstantin Genin

The distinction between deductive (infallible, monotonic) and inductive (fallible, non-monotonic) inference is fundamental in the philosophy of science. However, virtually all scientific inference is statistical, which falls on the inductive side of the traditional distinction. We propose that deduction should be nearly infallible and monotonic, up to an arbitrarily small, a priori bound on chance of error. A challenge to that revision is that deduction, so conceived, has a structure entirely distinct from ideal, infallible deduction, blocking useful analogies from the logical to the statistical domain. We respond by tracing the logical insights of traditional philosophy of science to the underlying information topology over possible worlds, which corresponds to deductive verifiability. Then we isolate the unique information topology over probabilistic worlds that corresponds to statistical verifiability. That topology provides a structural bridge between statistics and logical insi...

Theoretical Concepts and Hypothetico-Inductive Inference

Ilkka Niiniluoto

Adrian Currie

Experimentation is traditionally considered a privileged means of confirmation. However, how experiments are a better confirmatory source than other strategies is unclear, and recent discussions have identified experiments with various modeling strategies on the one hand, and with 'natural' experiments on the other hand. We argue that experiments aiming to test theories are best understood as controlled investigations of specimens. 'Control' involves repeated, fine-grained causal manipulation of focal properties. This capacity generates rich knowledge of the object investigated. 'Specimenhood' involves possessing relevant properties given the investigative target and the hypothesis in question. Specimens are thus representative members of a class of systems, to which a hypothesis refers. It is in virtue of both control and specimenhood that experiments provide powerful confirmatory evidence. This explains the distinctive power of experiments: although modellers exert extensive control, they do not exert this control over specimens; although natural experiments utilize specimens, control is diminished.

harold kincaid

Hans Radder

In this article, I put forward three basic philosophical claims concerning, or derived from, scientific experimentation. My discussion exploits the following core notions for the philosophical analysis of experimental practice: the aim of realizing object-apparatus correlations; the stages of preparation, interaction and detection; the dimensions of material realization and theoretical interpretation of experimental systems; the required control of the relevant interactions between environment and experimental system; and the different types and ranges of experimental reproducibility. The primary link with the Stanford school is the early work of Ian Hacking, especially his Representing and Intervening (1983). The first section offers some general remarks on the approach, impact, and strengths and weaknesses of this book. In the subsequent sections, I regularly return to Hacking´s views, partly endorsing, partly expanding and partly criticizing them. In these sections, I discuss and argue for the following philosophical claims. The significance of material realization implies that causation is an indispensable aspect of all experimental sciences (section 2). The required interpretation of the object-apparatus correlation entails the impossibility of a full 'compartmentalization' of the different kinds of theories employed in experimentation (section 3). Finally, reproducibility proves to be a significant aspect of experimental practices, but the 'double hermeneutic' limits its role in experimental social science and psychology (section 4).

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Philosophical Problems in Science

Marcin Gorazda

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews

Stephan Hartmann

James Woodward

Ingo Brigandt

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A

Michael T Stuart

Jean Claude Nsabimana

Elliott Sober

PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association

Deborah Mayo

Juan Calderon

Arseny Moskvichev

Metascience

William Peden

P.D. Magnus

Information

Julio Stern

Jonathan Livengood

AIP Conference Proceedings

tim eastman

Massimiliano Badino

Valeriano Iranzo

New Essays in Logic and Philosophy of Science (M. D’Agostino, G. Giorello, F. Laudisa, T. Pievani, C. Sinigaglia, eds.)

Luca Guzzardi

Frank Hindriks

European Journal for Philosophy of Science

Cristina Sagrafena

Dean Peters

Marie I. Kaiser

Matthew J. Brown

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT

a trial and error procedure built in a way that the outcome will conclude which of the two converse theories has postulated the accurate prediction.

Related terms:

  • Kaspar Hauser Experiment
  • Marshmellow Test (Marshmellow Experiment)
  • Bobo doll experiment
  • Milgram Experiment
  • ANALOGUE EXPERIMENT
  • MULTIPLC-CHOICC EXPERIMENT
  • EXPLORATORY EXPERIMENT
  • CASPAR HAUSER EXPERIMENT
  • BROOKLANDS EXPERIMENT

IMAGES

  1. PPT

    crucial experiment definition

  2. Experiment Definition in Science

    crucial experiment definition

  3. 100 Years Carnegie: Newton: the Crucial Experiment

    crucial experiment definition

  4. PPT

    crucial experiment definition

  5. What We've Learned from NKS Chapter 2: The Crucial Experiment

    crucial experiment definition

  6. The Crucial Experiment : A New Kind of Science

    crucial experiment definition

COMMENTS

  1. Experimentum crucis

    Experimentum crucis. In science, an experimentum crucis ( English: crucial experiment or critical experiment) is an experiment capable of decisively determining whether or not a particular hypothesis or theory is superior to all other hypotheses or theories whose acceptance is currently widespread in the scientific community.

  2. Crucial experiment

    crucial experiment. An experiment held to decide with certainty between two rival hypotheses about some matter. Famous examples include Eddington's observation of the bending of light rays by the sun during the eclipse of 1919, held to decisively uphold general relativity against Newtonian mechanics, or the observation of weight gain during ...

  3. Reinterpreting Crucial Experiments

    A crucial experiment is successful if it provides evidence that confirms one of the rivals and disconfirms the others. Special cases of successful crucial experiments are those in which the evidence verifies one of the rivals and refutes the others or those in which the evidence confirms one of the rivals and refutes the others.

  4. Crucial experiments

    A 'crucial experiment' allegedly establishes the truth of one of a set of competing theories. Francis Bacon held that such experiments are frequent in the empirical sciences and are particularly important for terminating an investigation.These claims were denied by Pierre Duhem (), who maintained that crucial experiments are impossible in the physical sciences because they require a ...

  5. Experimentum crucis: Newton's Empiricism at the Crossroads

    Here is a classical definition of 'crucial experiment' in Stanley Jevons: Such is the groundwork of similarity in nature, that two different conditions may often give closely similar results. We sometimes find ourselves therefore in possession of two or more hypotheses which both agree with so many experimental facts as to have great ...

  6. Scientific Objectivity

    Scientific objectivity is a property of various aspects of science. It expresses the idea that scientific claims, methods, results—and scientists themselves—are not, or should not be, influenced by particular perspectives, value judgments, community bias or personal interests, to name a few relevant factors. Objectivity is often considered ...

  7. The role of crucial experiments in science

    Role of Crucial Experiments in Science 317 including initial conditions and all sorts of auxiliary and observational theories. This is a very considerable withdrawal, for it allows the imaginative scientist to save his pet theory by suitable lucky alterations in some odd corner of the theoretical maze.

  8. Experiment in Physics

    3.2.1 A Crucial Experiment: The Discovery of Parity Nonconservation. Let us consider first an episode in which the relation between theory and experiment was clear and straightforward. This was a "crucial" experiment, one that decided unequivocally between two competing theories, or classes of theory.

  9. Experimentum Crucis/Instantia Crucis in the Seventeenth Century

    Definition. An experimentum crucis or instantia crucis is an experiment or set of observations which is held to be in some sense decisive in confirming or falsifying a theoretical explanation of a phenomenon. It is "crucial" not in the sense of being important but in the sense of bringing us to a signpost at a crossroads (a crux in Latin ...

  10. PDF The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and

    alleged 'crucial experiment' that is thought to have provided decisive evidence for one among a group of hypotheses. A well-known example is the Hershey-Chase experiment (1952), which showed that viral DNA, not protein, enters a bacterial cell to reprogram it to make virus particles. Another example is the 'PaJaMo' experiment (1958), which

  11. Underdetermination of Scientific Theory

    Underdetermination of Scientific Theory. First published Wed Aug 12, 2009; substantive revision Tue Apr 4, 2023. At the heart of the underdetermination of scientific theory by evidence is the simple idea that the evidence available to us at a given time may be insufficient to determine what beliefs we should hold in response to it.

  12. The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and Inference to the

    Going back at least to Duhem, there is a tradition of thinking that crucial experiments are impossible in science. I analyse Duhem's arguments and show that they are based on the excessively strong assumption that only deductive reasoning is permissible in experimental science. This opens the possibility that some principle of inductive inference could provide a sufficient reason for ...

  13. The Role of the Crucial Experiment

    The idea of a crucial experiment that decisively confirms a model goes back at least to Francis Bacon (1561 - 1626) who used the term instantia cruci. Later, the term experimentum crucis was coined by Robert Hooke (1635 - 1703) and used by Isaac Newton (1642 - 1727), in particular with regard to his theory of light.Alternatively, Pierre Duhem (1861 - 19 16) strongly disagreed with the ...

  14. Some epistemic implications of 'crucial experiments'

    Let us codify this understanding in the following definition Discussions 63 (D6) An experiment whose results are formulated by the proposition a is a `crucial experiment' if there are propositions h, a and f such that R(h & amf), R-(e &f), Re, R -f and R-(h & a). But are `crucial experiments' really crucial in any important sense?

  15. (PDF) The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and Inference

    alleged 'crucial experiment' that is thought to have provided decisive evidence for one among a group of hypotheses. A well-known example is the Hershey-Chase experiment

  16. What is CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT? definition of CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT

    Psychology Definition of CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT: a trial and error procedure built in a way that the outcome will conclude which of the two converse theories has

  17. The Role of Crucial Experiments in Science (Imre Lakatos, 1974)

    Natural light of experience is held by empiricists to be the reliable source of human knowledge. Inductive logic has been a leading tool of empirical experiments in justifying and confirming scientific theories with evidence. Science cannot reach where it has reached without inductive logic. Inductive logic has, therefore, played an important ...

  18. Conceptual Change, Crucial Experiments and Auxiliary ...

    The crucial experiment's legitimacy depends on the understanding of data and the theoretical context where the experience is interpreted ... However, due to its definition, inertia is unobservable because it would require an absolutely isolated body and the absence of any reference system to measure its movement without interference.

  19. What does experimentum crucis mean?

    Definition of experimentum crucis in the Definitions.net dictionary. Meaning of experimentum crucis. What does experimentum crucis mean? ... A "crucial experiment"; a conclusive test to decide between different hypotheses. Etymology: Modern Latin. Wikipedia Rate this definition: 0.0 / 0 votes. Experimentum crucis.

  20. The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and Inference to the

    Going back at least to Duhem, there is a tradition of thinking that crucial experiments are impossible in science. I analyse Duhem's arguments and show that they are based on the excessively strong assumption that only deductive reasoning is permissible in experimental science. This opens the possibility that some principle of inductive inference could provide a sufficient reason for ...

  21. Pierre Duhem

    Pierre Duhem (1861-1916) was a French physicist and historian and philosopher of science. As a physicist, he championed "energetics," holding generalized thermodynamics as foundational for physical theory, that is, thinking that all of chemistry and physics, including mechanics, electricity, and magnetism, should be derivable from thermodynamic first principles.

  22. The Crux of Crucial Experiments: Duhem's Problems and Inference to the

    On the account that I shall give, crucial experiments do not refute the alternatives. Instead, they positively select one of the hypotheses as best supported by the evidence. Therefore, Duhem's first problem in its classic form seems to be irrelevant. Even so, it is clearly the case that a crucial experiment relies on auxiliary assumptions.

  23. CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT Definition & Meaning

    CRUCIAL EXPERIMENT: "Crucial experiments are the simplest by nature and generally the first introduced in elementary or junior high science classes." x Twitter Facebook LinkedIn Reddit Messenger Telegram WhatsApp Email